Are Lawyers Different? —
Professional Resistance, Mandated Child Abuse Reporting and the Duty of
Confidentiality
Chrysanthi Leon*
Overview: Anxiety about child abuse combined with a general trend
towards placing the responsibility for crime control in the hands of the
public has led to a variety of changes in the laws surrounding child
abuse and sexual violence. This essay considers one of these
policy innovations — mandatory reporting laws — in light of the
professional duty of confidentiality to which attorneys must adhere, or
risk censure.1 California did
not pass an explicit exception to allow attorneys to violate
confidentiality until 2004, while other professions such as medicine,
the clergy and social work surrendered to a mandated reporting system
much earlier.
Are lawyers different? After considering the arguments for and
against maintaining attorneys’ discretion to violate confidentiality, as
well as the efficacy of mandated reporting, I argue that such discretion
should be preserved and perhaps returned to other professions.
Mandatory Reporting Laws and Their Context
Though social welfare movements had highlighted the
plight of children during earlier epochs in U.S. history, child abuse
became especially visible as an issue requiring public attention and
official response in the 1960s and 70s.2
In addition to insisting on better responses from law enforcement, the
awareness of child abuse as a social problem led to a push for private
citizens to take responsibility for recognizing and addressing violence
against children.3 The first
generation of reporting statutes focused on physicians; these were later
broadened to include other specified professionals likely to have contact
with children. Some statutes combined this approach with a catchall
category of reporters that could include anyone (Younes, 1987). In
1974, Congress enacted the Child Abuse and Prevention Act4
to provide federal funds for states that required reporting by certain
professionals. Today, in addition to prescribing criminal penalties
for failure to report, mandatory reporting laws typically provide immunity
against civil suits for those who do report.
As Robert Mosteller writes, the model legislation
which accompanied the Act and the statutes enacted by the various states
generally did not express an intention to fully include attorneys in the
reporting requirements, nor to explicitly over-ride the evidentiary rules
and confidentiality guidelines that protect the relationship between
attorneys and their clients (Mosteller (1992) 214). These laws have
however, created confusion as to the ultimate allegiances and
responsibilities of attorneys.
Aside from confusion over the duty to report, the
general trend towards aggressive responses to child abuse has not been
universally supported. Conservative think tanks, in particular,
voiced the concern that increased intervention of social services agencies
into situations of suspected abuse would lead to over-reporting and would
drain the resources of social service agencies. They further argued
that investigations into allegations of child abuse could invade “family
privacy,” which they argued should take primacy over consideration of the
child as an independent entity (Council 1992). Criticism has also
come from experts in the field of psychological theory and treatment.
Douglas Besharov, an authority on the treatment of child abuse, has been a
leading critic of what he considers overbroad and misguided legislation,
arguing that these laws wreak havoc by forcing professionals to file
unsubstantiated reports in order to avoid legal consequences (Besharov
1985).
Despite these criticisms, reporting policies have
become entrenched in our welfare system. Child abuse policies
continue to be debated in heated terms by both conservatives and
progressives, and the debate has been expanded to include the way child
sexual abuse, in particular, should be handled.
Beginning in the 1980s, public concern over the
prevalence of sexual abuse of children was widespread, with some asserting
that it was very common and others claiming that the threat was
exaggerated. Adult victims of child sexual abuse came forward with
allegations of abuse uncovered through regression therapy. There
were numerous revelations of sexual abuse and cover-ups by priests,
ministers and rabbis and by Boy Scout leaders, not to mention the McMartin
preschool hysteria. Several successful civil suits were brought
against religious groups that tried to cover up sexual abuse; damages paid
by the Catholic Church to victims of sexual abuse are estimated to exceed
$1 billion. Accusations of child pornography rings and Satanist
practices also popped up. Most, if not all, of these accusations
were disproved (Wright 1994). Criticism of recovered memory therapy
also grew, and those therapists who had supported it lost credibility, but
legal and social changes prompted by the moral panic remain largely in
place.
Though some of the changes instituted in order to
facilitate the prosecution of crimes against children have been rolled
back (such as some of the liberalizations of statutes of limitation
enacted in some states), many persist. Evidentiary rules in child
abuse cases continue to stretch traditional practice, allowing more leeway
for expert testimony, hearsay exceptions, and provisions for victim
testimony through technology such as video cameras (Poage 1991; Diab
2004).
In addition to changes in legal procedure, this time
period also saw a new innovation in law enforcement: community
notification laws. After the widely publicized murder of
seven-year-old Megan Kanka in 1994 by a convicted sex offender, Congress
passed legislation that required states to release information concerning
registered sex offenders (Pub. L. 104-236, 110 Stat.3093). The novel
part of this policy is the release of information about convicted sex
offenders to the public; previously, registries were for law enforcement
use only.
Community notification has some parallels to
mandated reporting — both are motivated by fear of crime and are premised
on the responsibility of community members to act on information made
available to them. As Jonathan Simon has argued, “Megan’s laws” in
some ways reflect a lessening accountability for government to address the
crime problem; instead, the state relies on the efforts of its citizens to
police themselves, motivated to do so out of fear of crime. (Simon 2000;
Simon & Leon forthcoming). Mandated reporting may have a similar genesis —
rising anxieties about a social problem which particularly horrifies us
have led us to look to each other, and to our professionals, for the
protection which the state has so far failed to provide.
The California Bar and the Debate over the Duty of Confidentiality
It was in this context of heightened anxiety and
drive for accountability that the American Bar Association passed Rule 1.6
in 1983, which states that a lawyer "may" reveal confidences if she
reasonably believes such revelation is necessary to prevent the client
from committing a criminal act that will result in death or substantial
bodily harm. (McCarthy 1997; Center for Professional Responsibility and
American Bar Association. House of Delegates. 2003). Rule 1.6 has
undergone some change since 1983, however: the language as amended in 2003
now separates the bodily harm clause from the criminal act clause, and
also contains a clause directing attorneys to “comply with the law” (Rule
1.6(b)(1-2; 6).
Two aspects of the original ABA model rule depart
from statutory mandated reporting: revelation is both voluntary and
prospective. Unlike reporting laws which require people to report
known cases of past (and potentially continuing) abuse, the ABA rule
allows the attorney to make a judgment call without fear of professional
discipline. Note, however, that the inclusion of the mandate to
violate confidentiality in order to “comply with the law” in the 2003
revision removes this discretion.
The ABA describes the confidentiality of the
attorney-client relationship as a “fundamental principle” and trust as a
“hallmark” of that relationship (Center for Professional Responsibility
and American Bar Association. House of Delegates. 2003) Comments to Rule
1.6, §2).
The California Bar began to grapple with how to
reconcile the requirements of law and professional ethics in 1987, when it
first requested new, clearer rules from the state Supreme Court.
California lawyers found themselves caught not only between the broad
reporting requirement and the duty of confidentiality, but also between a
more specific conflict of laws: California’s Business & Professions Code
§6068(e) (requiring lawyers to "maintain inviolate" client confidences)
and Evidence Code §956.5 (providing an exception when a lawyer believes a
client will commit a criminal act that will cause death or great bodily
harm).5 The Bar’s Committee on
Professional Responsibility and Conduct (COPRAC) withdrew their first
proposed clarification in 1987 in the face of court questions; the court
rejected a second without comment by the court in 1993 (McCarthy 1997).
In 1999, fear of crime against children factored
directly into the debate in California about a confidentiality exception,
when a media panic involving an abducted teen led Assembly Member Tony
Strickland to introduce the Kali Manley bill, AB 1286, to require lawyers
to share information about victims of abductions. Public outrage was
directed in particular at the suspect’s attorney, who was thought to have
information about the teen’s whereabouts that he did not reveal during the
search for her (Johnshon 1999), originally cited in Mohr 2002). The
original legislative proposal would have required this reporting only when
the information was requested from an attorney by law enforcement
officers. The text was later amended to require the report
independent of law enforcement involvement. Political will then
swung the other way and the last attempt to craft an acceptable statute
would have removed the mandatory requirement, stating that a lawyer could
voluntarily reveal such information.6
The bill ultimately failed (see further discussion below).
By 2002, every state except California had a
life-threatening criminal act exception (Mohr (2002) 310). Finally,
in 2004, the California legislature forced the issue, and rule 3-100 took
effect.7 Assembly Bill 1101 directed
the state to create an ethics rule which “reflected public policy.”
The new rule is worth considering in full, since it includes several
carefully crafted statements:
Rule 3-100. Confidential Information of a Client
(A) A member shall not reveal information protected from
disclosure by Business and Professions Code section 6068, subdivision
(e)(1) without the informed consent of the client, or as provided in
paragraph (B) of this rule.
(B) A member may, but is not required to, reveal confidential
information relating to the representation of a client to the extent that
the member reasonably believes the disclosure is necessary to prevent a
criminal act that the member reasonably believes is likely to result in
death of, or substantial bodily harm to, an individual.
(C) Before revealing confidential information to prevent a
criminal act as provided in paragraph (B), a member shall, if reasonable
under the circumstances:
(1) make a good faith effort to persuade the client: (i) not to
commit or to continue the criminal act or (ii) to pursue a course of
conduct that will prevent the threatened death or substantial bodily
harm; or do both (i) and (ii); and
(2) inform the client, at an appropriate time, of the member's
ability or decision to reveal information as provided in paragraph (B).
(D) In revealing confidential information as provided in
paragraph (B), the member's disclosure must be no more than is necessary
to prevent the criminal act, given the information known to the member at
the time of the disclosure.
(E) A member who does not reveal information permitted by
paragraph (B) does not violate this rule.
Like the ABA model rule, the California rule is
prospective and voluntary. However, the California rule is more
explicit in describing the mechanics of how violation of confidentiality
should take place. For example, consider an attorney advising a
client regarding a custody determination of a young child. The
client admits that her current boyfriend has abused the child in the past,
and continues to be near the child. An attorney following the
California rules has several choices. First, regardless of other
responses, he could — and arguably must — inform the client that allowing
the boyfriend continued access to the child might cause her to be charged
with criminal negligence of some kind. Then, he could do nothing
further, perhaps reasoning that the abuse is in the past. 3-100(b)
He could tell the client that she must remove the opportunity for future
abuse. (3-100(c)(1). He could inform the client that he planned to
file a report with Child Protective Services. 3-100(c)(2). While
California law does not view attorneys as mandated reporters, an attorney
may decide that such reporting is in the best interests of the child or
otherwise is the right thing to do — this will not fall under the purview
of Rule 3-100.8,9
The commentary to Rule 3-100 makes it clear that this final option is not
permitted if based only on the past acts:
Although a member is not permitted to reveal confidential information
concerning a client's past, completed criminal acts, the policy favoring
the preservation of human life that underlies this exception to the duty
of confidentiality and the evidentiary privilege permits disclosure to
prevent a future or ongoing criminal act.
In addition, once an attorney has violated confidentiality, the
commentary to Rule 3-100 states that “in all but extraordinary cases the
relationship between member and client will have deteriorated so as to
make the member's representation of the client impossible.
Therefore, the member is required to seek to withdraw from the
representation (cite omitted), unless the member is able to obtain the
client's informed consent to the member's continued representation”
(Discussion, para 11). After weighing the consequences of violating
confidentiality, an attorney may decide that he can do the family more
good by continuing representation than by filing a report, especially with
the common knowledge that many county departments of child protective
services are too overworked to follow through on all cases.
Ultimately, though Rule 3-100 clarifies the particular conflict of laws
which troubled California lawyers, it does not explicitly address the
problem of past abuse.
Facing this complex bundle of concerns, attorneys
may look for creative ways to ensure that reports are made by third
parties. For example, consider the approach suggested to a legal
ethics class by an attorney in a domestic violence practice. After
hearing the client describe her child’s account of abuse by her husband,
this attorney suggested her client call a child abuse hotline. The
attorney knew that if the mother shared the same information with the
advice line, a report would be triggered, but she did not tell the mother
(her client) this. Such misleading advice seems to violate the
spirit of the attorney-client relationship, if not the letter. ABA Model
Rule 2.1 (describing an attorney’s role as advisor). This example
suggests that California has not provided a clear path for attorneys faced
with such situations.
Comparing the Attorney’s Duty with the Clergy’s Limited Privilege
Before discussing in more detail how we might
reconcile the state’s interest in protecting children through a mandated
reporter system with the duty of confidentiality, it is worth a short
detour into a comparison between the way California law views attorneys
and clergy members with respect to their duties of confidentiality.
As discussed, attorneys are bound by a professional
duty to maintain their client’s confidences. Similarly, the leaders
of most religious congregations, including those who offer pastoral care,
hereinafter referred to as “clergy,” usually feel bound by their own
religious traditions to keep the confidences of those who seek their
counsel. Both attorneys and clergy are exempt from California’s
mandatory reporting laws, but nationally there is a great deal of
variability in whether clergy are explicitly included in reporting
statutes as well as uncertainty about whether clergy would be held liable
in practice for failing to report. Likely because of the Catholic
priest abuse scandals and perhaps also because clergy may be more likely
to encounter instances of abuse, there has been more judicial, legislative
and scholarly interest in the issue of a clergy exception to mandated
reporting schemes than in exceptions for attorneys.
California’s Child Abuse Reporting Act clearly
excludes clergy acting in a counseling role. The relevant section
reads:
A clergy member who acquires knowledge or a reasonable suspicion of
child abuse or neglect during a penitential communication is not subject
to subdivision (a)[which sets out the reporting requirement]. For
the purposes of this subdivision, "penitential communication" means a
communication, intended to be in confidence, including, but not limited
to, a sacramental confession, made to a clergy member who, in the course
of the discipline or practice of his or her church, denomination, or
organization, is authorized or accustomed to hear those communications,
and under the discipline, tenets, customs, or practices of his or her
church, denomination, or organization, has a duty to keep those
communications secret.
California Penal Code sec. 111666(d)(1)
But clergy are not excepted carte blanche. A
subsequent section clarifies that clergy who are not acting in what would
likely be read broadly as a counseling role (described in the statute as
engaged in “penitential communication”) but who are serving another role
which would bring them under the rubric of the reporting statute, such as
providing childcare or teaching Sunday school, would in fact be required
to report. From this vantage point, attorneys appear to have broader
protection, since the law does not limit their ability to maintain
confidentiality based on the particular function they are carrying out.
Instead, as discussed above, lawyers may report continuing abuse, but are
never compelled to report.10
Early into the child sex abuse panic, Professor Mary
Mitchell explored the rationale for the clergy exception, noting in
passing that the rationale for respecting attorney client confidences, in
contrast, was generally considered “weak.” Despite her assertion, a
more extended comparison between the two sets of rationales may help
illuminate on how and why lawyers are “different.”
Mitchell offers three categories of justification
for protecting the penitential relationship. First, Mitchell
considers society’s interest in preserving the relationship, using
Wigmore’s four-part test as a guide:
(1) Whether the communications are intended to confidential;
(2) Whether this element of confidentiality is essential to the
relation between the parties;
(3) Whether the relation is one which the community believes is
necessary; and
(4) Whether the disclosure would be more harmful to that relation than
the benefit that would be gained from disclosure (Wigmore 1961, 2258, as
cited in Mitchell at 762).
The key consideration is the balance between the social benefit of the
clergy relationship as weighed against the social benefit of triggering a
report of child abuse. While Mitchell easily finds the balance
tipped in favor of the clergy relationship, this outcome is more
controversial than she would allow. One wonders how a court, faced
with a prosecution of a member of the clergy for non-compliance with the
reporting statute, would determine how public opinion views this balance?
In light of decreasing church attendance in many segments of the
population, combined with the disaffection with the Catholic Church caused
by the abuse scandals, public opinion may not clearly value the
clergy-penitent relationship over the perceived benefits of reporting
child abuse. While the benefits of the clergy relationship may
include spiritual and emotional health and well-being, it is hard to
justify the exemption for clergy, who often are untrained in clinical
skills and unevenly trained in counseling compared to other therapeutic
professionals. Further, when considering the training that attorneys
receive for their work as well as the interests of life, liberty and
property which they protect, there seems to be a more obvious social
interest in the attorney-client relationship.
But Mitchell presents two more rationales for the
clergy exemption which do not apply to the attorney-client relationship.
Mitchell offers an interpretation of the right to privacy as found by the
Court since Roe which she feels could justify protecting the
intimate conversations between a spiritual advisor and advisee (770-777).11
While this argument might similarly made for other therapeutic
relationships, as above, it is possible that Americans find a peculiar
intimacy in spiritual conversations, worth more than the
often-embarrassing information regarding criminal or other liable behavior
that a client might communicate to legal counsel. But Mitchell’s
strongest argument for the unique value of the clergy exception is her
reading of its viability as a constitutional right, grounded primarily in
the non-establishment clause of the first amendment (798-823).12
In 1813, in the first case of its kind, a New York court found that a
Catholic priest could refuse to violate penitential confidences because
the Constitutional protected his freedom of religion (People v. Phillips,
(N.Y. Ct. Gen. Sess. 1813), an unpublished opinion discussed in Mitchell
at 737). Grounding an exception in such a culturally-valued
constitutional right clearly distinguishes clergy from attorneys.
In summary, some reasons for protecting confidences
are stronger for clergy while others are stronger for attorneys, with no
obvious reason for California’s more circumscribed protection of the
clergy-penitent relationship. This discussion provides an
introduction to a more sustained analysis of the attorney’s duty of
confidentiality.
Contradictions and Confusions: Reconciling Mandated or Elective Reporting
with the Duty of Confidentiality
In his exploration of what he sees as an age of
“experimentation” with lawyers as “crime detectors and informants,”
Mosteller poses a variation on the hypothetical described above (at 7-8,
describing a client in a custody case with an abusive boyfriend).13
Mosteller reads the hypothetical as having an uncertain message: does it
compromise the ability of the attorney to do his job and to protect
clients? Does it provide an opportunity for bringing an abusive
situation to light that otherwise would go unaddressed?
Empirical research has not addressed how these sorts
of situations work out in practice, nor do we know how often attorneys
report child abuse.14 Clearly, every
attorney can now make the choice to report such crime, and face the
professional consequences, if any.15
In California, those consequences are no longer an issue, as long as the
reporting is about a prospective crime that may cause substantial bodily
harm (see previous discussion of how child abuse fits that definition,
infra). In 18 states (excluding California), mandatory reporting
laws apply to all citizens, including lawyers, so lawyers in these states
would potentially face criminal penalties for not reporting.16
But should California follow the model of states like Mississippi, Nevada,
Ohio and Oregon and specifically compel lawyers to report? I
consider the arguments for and against.
Lawyers ARE Different: Against Mandated Reporting
Postponing, for now, a discussion of the Bar’s
interest as a profession to retain a unique status, there are several
reasons why the kind of work that lawyers do for their clients makes
mandatory reporting risky. Many of these reasons are described in
commentary to the model rules and in the debate about California’s rule
3-100.
First among these reasons for preserving
confidentiality is concern over the “freezing effect” that mandatory
reporting might have on the attorney-client relationship. Our
adversarial system is based upon the notion that the client will share all
relevant information with her advocate. As the ABA Commentary to
Rule 1.6 states, “The lawyer needs this information to represent the
client effectively and, if necessary, to advise the client to refrain from
wrongful conduct.”
Evidence of this kind of chilling effect is easily
found in the literature describing other professionals who are mandated
reporters. My own participant observation with therapists also
provides many examples of the perceived harm to the therapeutic
relationship caused by mandated reporting. For example, therapists
who work with sex offenders generally believe that honesty and
accountability for past crimes is a precondition for treatment. But
without the ability to assure confidentiality,17
clients may refuse to participate. (see, e.g., U.S. v. Antelope,
describing a probationer’s refusal to incriminate himself despite his
desire for therapy).
In declaring their opposition to the modification
later enacted as rule 3-100, several attorneys went on legislative record
about similar concerns. This bill, they argued, will create inherent
conflicts of interests between lawyers and their clients and between an
attorney's duties to his or her client and the new duties (of disclosure)
to non-clients. (Kim 2003). Note that this strong concern was
expressed about the rule which clarified that lawyers may report
prospective crime.
Mosteller adds an additional caution regarding
mandatory reporting of child abuse: what would prevent expansion of the
reporting requirement into other areas of repetitive crime? Although
current cultural preoccupations center on sex crime and violence against
children, recidivism statistics show much higher rates of re-offending for
other kinds of crimes. We might arguably prevent more crime and
cause greater social welfare by requiring attorneys to report other kinds
of criminal behavior as well.
Finally, recall the original rationale behind
mandated reporting: those professionals most likely to be in contact with
children and therefore in a position to observe evidence of harm should
report. If all of those mandated reporters are doing their duty, it
seems unlikely that a report would not already have been produced by the
time an attorney discovers harm to a child. So perhaps we should
work harder to enforce penalties against current reporters rather than
expanding the requirement.
Mandating that Lawyers Report
The most compelling argument that lawyers are
different and therefore should not report has to do with the need to
preserve the advocate’s ability to protect the client’s interests.
These interests may range from property interests to liberty or even life.
Lawyers argue that such high stakes skew the balance away from society’s
interest in protecting children.
But what about the interest in medical,
psychological or spiritual care? Situations which threaten the
patient/client’s life are more likely to occur in these contexts than in
the legal arena. If doctors must provide life-saving care to
patients who may not be honest about their own risky or violent behavior
then surely lawyers can similarly work out ways to provide the best
service they can to their clients. In fact, while it is arguable
that in certain situations, for example criminal defense, lawyers may
craft a better legal strategy without being fully informed, it is
difficult to imagine an analogy in the medical or psychological arena.
If we recognize that not nearly enough is being done
to protect children from harm, then bringing attorneys into the mandatory
reporting system seems worth the potential chilling effect on the
attorney-client relationship. Many of our legal and ethical values
as a society recognize the need to balance competing interests. We
may determine that the chance to save children from harm outweighs our
concern for preserving the rights associated with the adversarial system.
Broadening the Confidentiality Exception for Child Abuse
A compromise measure that would maintain the duty of
confidentiality and also address our concern for children would be to
broaden the exception. Instead of requiring a continuing or
prospective threat of serious bodily injury, perhaps we should explicitly
allow lawyers to violate confidentiality in order to report any knowledge
they may have about past crimes that involve children. This
preserves the ability of attorneys to make the choice to report or not,
but also protects them from professional censure. It would also
prevent the kind of maneuvering described by the domestic violence
attorney who violated the spirit of professional ethics, allowing
attorneys to take responsibility for reports they believe should be made
without finding creative ways to shift that responsibility to others.
Conclusion: The Professional Interest in Maintaining Discretion
Regardless of opinion as to the policy decision, it
is worth considering how the legal profession avoided inclusion in the
mandatory reporting system while so many others did not. A
structural/functionalist account of the Bar as a profession would credit
society with recognizing the role professions play as social glue.
It would further acknowledge the need for an independent Bar to act as
gatekeepers for our individual liberties. But as discussed above,
these arguments fail to distinguish attorneys from other professions which
also perform vital functions.
A Weberian account provides a more satisfying
explanation. Weber’s discussion of the system of professions,
elaborated by contemporary sociologists such as Andrew Abbott, explains
that the protection and privilege attached to professional status is
maintained through conflict (Abbott 1988). This conflict centers on
controlling boundaries, especially the boundaries of knowledge and
expertise, such as the ABA’s control of the accreditation of law schools.
Professions maintain themselves through an asymmetry of expertise: the
client must trust the professional and the professional must respect the
client and her colleagues; these relations are guaranteed by institutional
forms such as associations, licensure requirements and ethics codes.
Abbot explains that a profession maintains
jurisdiction in three ways, legal jurisdiction, social jurisdiction and
control over the actual work. Id. at 60-63. The first two are
clearly implicated by the conflict between the duty of confidentiality and
a system of mandated reporting. Legal jurisdiction is formal control
of work. This bears on the fact that it is the lawyer’s professional
code of ethics that controls in California, not a legislatively or
popularly imposed mandatory reporting law.18,19
Public jurisdiction describes a claim for legitimate control of a
particular kind of work, to do work as the profession wishes, and to
exclude other workers, "Public jurisdiction, in short, is a claim of both
social and cultural authority" (Abbot, 60). So the ability of
attorneys to practice law as they wish, free of reporting requirements,
reflects substantial social and cultural authority. This account
relies on the assertion that as a society we believe in lawyers and their
expertise, and as a result we accept that they know best how to determine
when and if to violate confidentiality.
One indication of this strength is the defeat of the
Kali Manley bill, discussed above. Considering the strength of the
victim’s rights movement, especially when it acts in concert with law
enforcement and with the power of public outrage behind it, it is truly
remarkable that no version of the Kali Manley bill passed into law.
One would not expect the criminal defense bar to wield the kind of power
it did in order to resist this pressure; this is a testament to the power
of the profession.
In sum, lawyers have largely resisted inclusion in
mandatory reporting schemes because they are a powerful profession, with a
strong claim of expertise that we are reluctant to interfere with.
So lawyers may be “different” in terms of their power to defend against
intrusions on their jurisdiction.
Is this a difference worth preserving?
Mandatory reporting is still something of an
experiment in terms of its impact on public safety and the protection of
vulnerable populations. Until we can assert with conviction that
requiring doctors, teachers and dental hygienists to report leads to
beneficial consequences, there is little reason to bring attorneys under
the umbrella as well. Thus, whether or not lawyers are different,
expansion of mandated reporting does not have a rational justification.
In fact, if lawyers’ “difference” is their professional power, perhaps
discretion should be returned to health and education personnel as well.
Footnotes