"I Am Not a Doctor But I Play One on TV": An Essay/Review of
Galileo's Revenge
() by Peter Huber1
Jack Zusman*
ABSTRACT: Peter Huber's book, Galileo's Revenge, is
reviewed and the problems with expert testimony are discussed.
Suggestions are made as to how to make expert witnesses more responsible
and accountable.
"I am not a doctor but I play one on TV." Most of us
have seen the distinguished looking older gentleman in his white coat as
he makes a pitch in a TV commercial for an over-the-counter
medication. That this commercial has run so widely across the
country and for so long suggests its strong appeal. The appeal
plays upon the awe which most people have for scientists and
physicians. Indeed, the authors of that commercial are so sure of
the power of the medical halo that after dressing their star in a white
coat, they brazenly do not hesitate to begin his script with the
truthful statement that he is not a doctor but only play acts as
one. They are confident that the strength of his image will
overcome the truth of his words.
We live in an age where there is enormous respect for scientists but
little for scientific knowledge. The medication commercial makes
no attempt to report scientific evidence of the superior effectiveness
of the product (if any exists). Rather it attempts to make the
audience think that evidence must exist after all, would the
"doctor" dare to stand there looking so professional and
speaking so authoritatively if he was not telling the truth?
The result is a competition among advertisers over scientific
appearance or superficial believability rather than medication safety
and effectiveness. Fortunately (or unfortunately, depending upon
your perspective) being a scientist requires more than putting on a
white coat and having gray hair and a mustache. Carrying out
scientific procedures means adhering strictly to certain procedural
rules and when those rules are followed the resulting conclusions are
likely to be correct. Certainly one of the key strengths of the
American economy is the centrality of science. Yet science is both
expensive and uncomfortable to carry out. The rules are hard to
follow. What a temptation it is to claim the benefits of science
without having to endure the costs.
Such a shortcut is so attractive that sometimes even scientists
engage in it. But regardless of who attempts to benefit from the
reputation of science while avoiding all of the scientific constraints,
such a practice is expensive for all of us. When the
"facts" which are claimed to be "scientific" are
revealed as false, the revelation reduces respect for science and
confuses the large majority of the people who are not scientists.
They see they can no longer take for granted that something labeled as
science is true. The reputation and the language of science have
been degraded.
Peter Huber has written an examination of this pseudo or "junk
science" phenomenon as it occurs in the courtroom, particularly in
civil trials such as negligence or workers' compensation. Using
court transcripts and appellate opinions, newspaper articles, anecdotes,
and similar historical materials he has demonstrated very well how
illogical and downright silly both judges and juries can be in some of
the decisions they have made apparently in response to testimony by
presumed scientists.
For example, one patient won payment for developing cancer of the jaw
which he and his experts convinced a jury was from cutting his lip on a
cardboard carton (Huber, 1991, p.47). Another group of individuals
was awarded $49,000,000 in damages for being exposed to chemicals from a
nearby soap and cosmetics plant (p. Huber, 1991, p. 97). The
symptoms in question included "nerve damage and heart disease,
brain damage and vomiting, kidney infections and headaches. Young
women reported interrupted menstrual cycles ... dogs, cats, cattle,
chickens, parakeets and bee colonies died 'unaccountably and without
signs of predation'." One expert testifying for the
plaintiffs in this case blamed the damage on the immune system being
"functionally wiped out." Though testifying as an expert
on the immune system, he had never taken a course in immunology.
Another of the experts in this case failed his board exam in Internal
Medicine five times and withdrew from the exam twice. But he
testified that he took the exam only once and later explained he had
forgotten about the other times (Huber, 1991, p.92).
Then there was the $5,100,000 verdict against the Ortho company
because its spermicidal cream was determined by a court after expert
testimony to be at fault in causing birth defects (Huber, 1991,p.
174). The testimony was apparently based on one study which
suggested spermicides "might" cause birth defects and the
authors of the study later essentially repudiated the findings.
In the context of this journal are a number of well-publicized cases
where persons claiming mental health professional expertise of some sort
had major roles in initiating and/or keeping legal actions going against
presumed child abusers. No matter how unlikely the charges or weak
the scientific evidence, these experts were willing to swear to the
truth of the charges solely on the basis of psychological findings or
esoteric physical evidence not corroborated or considered valid by any
other professional. Some experts were willing to swear that
children making abuse charges never lie, although a moment's thought
should have made it clear to them that such a statement had to be way
beyond anyone's scientific expertise since the necessary studies had
never been done.
Recently in Hanover Park, Illinois, a man was arrested after being
charged by a five-year-old next door neighbor of forcing her to witness
the murder of five young girls in his bedroom and of the murder of a man
in the basement (The Economist, 1991). The murdered man was
then allegedly partially eaten by the accused and his wife. A
mental health counselor, an expert in satanic sexual abuse, had worked
with the five-year-old who was the only witness to the alleged crimes.
The case was eventually dismissed by the judge for lack of credible
evidence but consider what damage must have been done to the accused,
his wife, and all those around them. Indeed, the accuser also was
probably damaged by having to go through the accusatory process rather
than having what seem to be her childish nightmares dealt with as such.
Much of the questionable expert testimony Huber is concerned with has
been based on work outside the scientific mainstream and/or by an
"expert" whose expertise, if any, would not be recognized as
legitimate by most scientists. Time and time again, liability has
been found in lawsuits where scientific knowledge strongly suggests the
damage could not have occurred as claimed. Regardless, the courts
found for the plaintiff. The result has been large monetary
awards.
For criminal defendants or those in the area of law where punitive
measures can be taken against civil defendants divorce and child
custody use of these experts can lead to false accusation,
loss of reputation, the enormous expense of presenting a defense, and
the greatest risk of all: losing the case and facing the penalties on
the basis of incompetent testimony from a junk scientist
Huber's focus is less on the decision makers themselves and more on
the parts played in the decisions by expert witnesses who have testified
in support of a damage claim. We learn from his descriptions that
many of these damage claims are exaggerated, nonexistent, or come from
some cause other than the one claimed. Often a plaintiff's lawyer
has searched diligently to find some person who could be made out to
have scientific credentials and who would be willing to attempt to
convince the jury regardless that mainstream science would not
agree. The result has been unfairness, misallocation of resources,
and tremendous increases in liability insurance costs. In some
cases, such as those involving vaccines and medications, manufacturers
have subsequently discontinued production despite a need and a good
market rather than face more lawsuits.
One problem with all of this is that Huber does not tell us how
frequently such misadventures occur in comparison to the total number of
cases. By picking on horrible examples and implying they are
typical, he may be committing the same sin he demonstrates many
"experts" do confusing what can happen with what
is likely to happen.
Huber's thesis is that there has been a significant deterioration in
the scientific qualifications of expert witnesses testifying in court
and of the scientific quality of the testimony. At present, judges
in many jurisdictions, including Federal courts, will allow testimony
from just about any person who can be at all justified as having
scientific credentials. The extent or nature of the scientific
underpinning of experts' opinions are not scrutinized by the
judge. Weaknesses are left to exposure through cross examination
by the opposing side if the opposing attorney gets around to
it. Any kind of expert testimony can get in front of the
jury. As a result, attorneys place a premium on experts'
believability i.e. talent at impressing a jury rather than
on scientific knowledge.
The charismatic, attractively dressed and coiffed individual who
speaks convincingly will inevitably outweigh the highly skilled,
knowledgeable, mainstream scientist who looks and speaks the way most of
us do. And if the good looking expert should testify to something
which is in line with common beliefs of the moment or fads no matter how
outlandish, then truth and knowledge have hardly a chance. Form
inevitably overcomes substance.
This is a serious problem for all of us because we all need a
dependable legal system, whether we happen to have to go to court or
not. We need the legal system to be fair to reach the best
possible judgment regardless of the personal characteristics or
sympathetic appearance of the individuals involved. We expect the
system to be reality based that when a decision is reached, the
decision is based upon something which really did happen and not on the
imagination or mistaken theories of some person or some group.
When an event is attributed to a particular cause, we expect that the
cause really did precipitate the event.
We expect the legal system to be predictable so that what was legally
acceptable yesterday is going to be legally acceptable tomorrow or else
how can people who wish to be law abiding govern their behavior?
We also expect trials to have fairly predictable outcomes so that
lawbreakers cannot feel that even if caught they can gamble on a lottery
and have a good chance to go unpunished. Accused persons who are
innocent should not have to feel they must trust to luck for
exoneration. A legal system which uses experts whose expertise may
never be properly evaluated, and whose expert opinions may be based on
no more than personal belief or untested theory cannot be relied upon to
be fair, just, or predictable.
What is the role of the expert in a legal system if final judgment is
left to a jury of peers? Though the legal decision process heavily
weights the experience and common sense of the average person, it also
recognizes that the average person does not have sufficient knowledge or
experience in certain issues to be able to arrive at a just
decision. For example, if a trial hinges on whether or not a
defendant is mentally ill, the average juror will have knowingly
encountered perhaps two or three mentally ill people in a
lifetime. This is not a large enough experience to make an
informed decision. The jurors can be assisted by someone who has
seen hundreds of mentally ill persons and has learned to use
demonstrably effective methods of recognizing and categorizing mental
illness.
However as Huber emphasizes, the use of experts has brought problems
as well as advantages. And the more freedom experts have been
given, the more problems there have been. From 1923 to 1975
Federal courts (which tend to set the standards for state courts)
permitted experts to testify only if their opinions were based upon
theories and procedures which were within the scientific
mainstream. This considerably limited the manner in which
attorneys could use experts in trials because even if the attorney could
find an expert to support a far out claim, the judge would not permit
the expert to testify.
In 1975 the Federal Rules of Evidence were written to allow any
expert testimony as long as it assisted the judge or jury to understand
the evidence or determine a fact. For good or for bad this opened
the door for experts to have an expanded role in the courts.
Presumably the safeguard against unqualified experts or outlandish
opinions would be cross examination by the opposing lawyer who would
bring out the weaknesses for the jury to see.
What this failed to consider is that few attorneys are scientifically
sophisticated enough to cross examine an expert and expose gross error
or incompetence. The best many attorneys seem to hope for is to
use their own experts to confuse the jury to the point that the
testimony of one expert cancels the effects of the other regardless of
the differing acceptability of their views. And of course both
experts and attorneys have learned to make use of appearance and manner
of presentation over substance. So there is little protection of
the decision making process from well presented but incorrect or
inadequately based expert opinions.
Huber certainly makes the point with his anecdotes that there is a
problem. Where the book is weak is on proposing solutions to the
problem. Huber barely goes beyond making clear that he is in favor
of going back to some method of distinguishing mainstream science from
fringe science. The mechanism through which this could be
accomplished is problematic. In an era of great scientific
complexity, how can judges know which experts to exclude? We could
set up official bodies to represent the various scientific fields and
have them determine who is to be accredited to the courts, or require
some sort of high level credential for an expert to be able to appear in
court. Indeed serious proposals of these sorts have been made and
discussed.
Junk science in the courtroom though is a more complex problem than
Huber recognizes. Many factors are at work. Even if
permitting only mainstream scientists to testify yielded some
improvement, it would be far from a satisfactory solution. A
number of other issues must be tackled as well.
First we do not want to repeat the Galileo problem. As Huber
reminds us in the in the book's title, Galileo is the prime example of
the damage which can be done when representatives of mainstream science
decide who can speak up. Galileo developed a theory that the earth
revolved around the sun certainly not mainstream science at the
time. To their eternal discredit, the powers that be forced him to
recant his "error."
Indeed, mainstream science can go terribly wrong, particularly in the
social or behavioral sciences, where much of the courtroom action is
these days. To take an example from history much more recent than
Galileo, look at the mainstream adherence to Freudian theories of
psychopathology for a period of close to 50 years. How many
predictions have been made of terrible damage to children because of
witnessing "the primal scene." (For those too young to
have lived through the Freudian era, the primal scene involves seeing
one's parents engaged in sexual intercourse.) Yet at the time
there was not a shred of statistical or even good clinical evidence that
this damage could occur. (Nor of course is there any better
evidence now.)
How many cases of schizophrenia were attributed to schizophrenogenic
mothers simply on the basis of an untested theory? Furthermore,
one can hardly think of a more rigidly defined and enforced mainstream
than analytically-oriented psychiatry and psychology. Highly
trained and respected colleagues were disgraced and ostracized for minor
theoretical deviations. The presence or absence of experimental
evidence in support of theoretical positions was never even an
issue. We would not want to turn control over what can be said in
a courtroom to mainstream groups of this sort. Galileo's Revenge
might better be called Galileo's Paradox or Galileo's Dilemma: how do we
avoid junk science in the courtroom without foreclosing the opportunity
to hear new, developing, and ultimately correct ideas?
Second is the fact that experts are in no way accountable for what
they say in court and therefore improper testimony is not
penalized. Experts are free to say whatever they please in the
knowledge that there likely will be no personal consequences regardless
of how misleading their testimony eventually turns out to be.
Human nature being what is, even legitimate experts may be tempted to
go beyond their scientific knowledge. This is in contrast to the
situation when psychiatrists or psychologists provide clinical
services. There they have strict codes of professional ethics to
follow and concerns about loss of professional licenses or liability
lawsuits for misbehavior. Though perhaps in principle what experts
say in court might lead to charges of unethical behavior or to a
negligence lawsuit, such charges or lawsuits just about never
occur. And because of the adversarial manner in which we structure
trials, experts are encouraged if not required to defend their testimony
strongly while not mentioning any uncertainties or loopholes they are
aware of in what they are proposing. Though the courtroom oath to
tell the whole truth and professional ethics might seem to require
expressing such doubts (particularly the ethical code of the American Psychological Association),
these are universally ignored without penalty.
The legal system also discourages acknowledgement of the shades of
uncertainty with which science deals all the time. Few legitimate
scientists would defend any theory or conclusion as absolutely and
ultimately correct. The best science ever achieves is a high level
of probability and scientists spend a lot of time attempting to punch
holes in that probability. Most scientific conclusions are
tentative and accepted only until something better comes along.
The law in contrast looks for definitive statements of yes or no with
nothing in between. To play the legal game, the expert must assert
a certainty with which most scientists are uncomfortable. Failing
to be so assertive or attempting to qualify a courtroom opinion will
usually lead to damage to the side the expert is trying to support,
particularly when the expert on the other side has no such
scruples. So for example, a cause and effect relationship which in
the view of the conscientious expert is no more than possible becomes
transmuted on the witness stand to inevitable and unquestionable.
Additionally, the sense of professional responsibility, pride, and
allegiance to scientific principles which in past years governed what
experts would say in the name of science, seems no longer to be as
effective. Concern over damaging the public's image of science or
making oneself appear ridiculous in the eyes of colleagues seems for
some individuals to be outweighed by the fame and fortune to be gained
as a successful expert witness. Impressing a jury, pleasing a
lawyer, establishing a reputation as a witness who can win a case and
therefore make a lot of money seem to be career goals for some.
Others look for the opportunity to get a public stamp of approval from a
judge and jury for a theory which no panel of legitimate scientists
would accept. Still others seem to be on a crusade to improve the
world, using their scientific credentials as weapons against sacrificial
victims to advance a cause.
Third is the fact that though expert witnesses are usually hired by
one side or the other, they are supposed to be neutral, advocating in
the courtroom only for scientific truth. Neutrality is often at
best what has been called a legal fiction. Once an expert becomes
involved with a case, interacts at length with the legal team, prepares
to defend the findings in court, etc. the expert in effect becomes part
of the legal team. As one observer put it, thinking that an expert
can remain neutral is like thinking someone can sit on the bench with a
basketball team in the middle of a hotly fought game and not root for
that team. Furthermore, a single expert may be employed not only
to testify in court but to advise the attorneys on courtroom strategy
and help the attorneys prepare to attack the opposing expert
hardly neutral scientific functions.
Finally is the tendency of experts to offer opinions on issues where
they have no expertise. Like most human beings, experts have
strongly held personal opinions on many subjects, opinions they offer
freely when asked. Few experts seem ever to decline to offer an
opinion in court even when that opinion is not on a scientific
matter. When an expert speaks on a moral, ethical, or even factual
matter, despite the. expert's lack of scientific authority, the expert's
opinion is usually accorded great weight by the jury. Many
experts, untrained in the nuances of courtroom procedure, may not even
be aware of how they are going beyond the appropriate limits of their
testimony. Here again, the major barrier to this occurrence should
be the opposing attorney but the opposing attorney often seems not to be
aware of the issue nor interested in responding.
For anyone concerned with having an effective and just legal system,
the current use of expert witnesses is painful to contemplate. To
be sure, many minor, unpublicized cases are swiftly and properly
handled. But there are enough disgraceful cases around to make
improvement mandatory.
But what improvements seem both worthwhile and feasible? As
already mentioned, such suggestions are probably the weakest part of
Huber's book and for good reason. The expert witness
situation is so interwoven in the fabric of modern American law and has
so many interest groups to defend it, this maybe one of those situations
were "you cannot get there from here." Nevertheless,
here are a few thoughts about steps which seem to be doable with only
modest disruption and which would produce considerable improvement.
First, make experts accountable in some way for what they say in
court. One way to do this would be to change the laws of each
state so as to define service as an expert witness as professional
practice. Experts could then not only be more easily sued for
negligence as an expert but could also lose their professional licenses
for improper behavior. Such an approach would discourage much of
the unreasonable testimony by experts but would not shut off innovation
nor solidify control by mainstream professional organizations.
Second, increase the specialization of attorneys and require complex
cases involving scientific issues to be handled by attorneys competent
in that area. Though at one time any attorney felt prepared to
take on any kind of case, this is no longer so. Legal specialties
have evolved and many attorneys will not take a case outside their area
of competence. However, specialization has not reached the point
where scientific issue cases require a specialist. Perhaps that
point should be here. At the least, generalist attorneys taking on
such cases ought to use appropriate consultants. Only with the
benefit of such assistance or of their own specialized knowledge can
attorneys explore adequately the scientific bases of expert testimony
during cross examination. The U.S. Supreme Court has recently
ruled that attorneys dealing with death penalty defenses where mental
illness is an issue have a right to consultation on the case from
psychiatrists. The significance of this ruling is that it
recognizes the role of the expert consultant in assisting the attorney
to do the attorney's job, not just in testifying in court.
Finally, is the elimination of the legal fiction that the expert is
neutral. Recognize the reality that the expert becomes part of the
legal team and that in court the expert is not swearing that something
did or did not happen but is describing only how something could have
happened provided the claim by the expert's client is accepted as
true. In this approach, the expert is the explainer of scientific
theory as it applies to the presumed facts of the case but not the
certifier of the facts. Conflict between experts for the two sides
would then be over the likelihood that one theory or another is
applicable in the situation but not over who is telling the truth.
Experts' expertise is appropriately used in evaluating scientific
theory. It is for the jury to sort out competing claims.
Peter Huber has written a thought provoking book.
Unfortunately, it only sets the scene for the work that remains to be
done. But considering the difficulty of the task, this is about
all we can ask for at this time. This book is certainly worth
reading by anyone who is concerned with the use of scientific expertise
in the courtroom.
References
Huber, P. W. (1991). Galileo's Revenge: Junk Science in the
Courtroom
().
New York: Basic Books.
The Economist, August
31st, 1991, p. 23.